Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
Skip to main content
This is a DRAFT (22-07-31) book chapter; its final version is to be published in the upcoming Handbook of Qur'anic Hermeneutics, edited by Georges Tamer. The chapter is organized as follows: 1. The hermeneutical background of Shaykh... more
This is a DRAFT (22-07-31) book chapter; its final version is to be published in the upcoming Handbook of Qur'anic Hermeneutics, edited by Georges Tamer. The chapter is organized as follows:

1. The hermeneutical background of Shaykh Aḥmad, his biography, and his legacy.

2. A selection and discussion of some key works of Shaykh Aḥmad that pertain to the hermeneutics and tafsīr of the Qur'an. This includes a brief discussion of the controversial question of transposition (taḥrīf).

3. A detailed discussion of Shaykh Aḥmad's framework of theory and practice of hermeneutics. This includes matters such as

i) The necessary and sufficient conditions of hermeneutics,
ii) the two types of inferential indicator (dalīl) that apply to hermeneutics,

4. Detailed application of the framework of theory and practice to a real-life hermeneutical problem: Do certain Āyāt make reference to Lady Fiḍḍah, the handmaiden and close confidant of Fāṭimah (ʿa)?

5. Discussion of the six fundamental levels of tafsīr: the outward (ẓāhir) and the outward of the outward (ẓāhir al-ẓāhir); the inward (bāṭin) and the inward of the inward (bāṭin al-bāṭin); the symbolic (taʾwīl) and the inward of the symbolic (bāṭin al-taʾwīl).
[This DRAFT book chapter is virtually complete. A slightly edited version of this chapter has been submitted and approved for publication in the forthcoming volume The Philosophical Legacy of Jorge J.E. Gracia, scheduled to be published... more
[This DRAFT book chapter is virtually complete. A slightly edited version of this chapter has been submitted and approved for publication in the forthcoming volume The Philosophical Legacy of Jorge J.E. Gracia, scheduled to be published in 2021by Rowman & Littlefield.]

Abstract: The question of development and its place in the world is one of the oldest in the history of metaphysics. In the course of the formative years of the discipline that culminated in the metaphysical views of Plato and Aristotle, Heraclitus’ emphasis on development qua concrete unity of process and result eventually gave way to a commitment to identify, in one degree or other of abstraction from becoming, the fundamental locus of reality, intelligibility, and goodness with being per se. Classic examples include Plato’s absolutely separate and timeless forms as well as Aristotle’s absolutely immutable and distinct infimae species (including both immaterial and materiate forms), in terms of which his closely related theory of scientific demonstration is constructed.

Despite its subordination, the theme of development, even in the realm of presumably immaterial and timeless being, was never entirely neglected – important Islamaic and Christian metaphysicians often emphasized the active and dynamic as opposed to static nature of pure being or existence. Eventually, however, the categories of what later Christian metaphysicians would come to call “general metaphysics”, and later Islamaic metaphysicians “general matters”, would become increasingly ossified, static, and conceived in ever greater abstraction from the intelligible realities, which are intrinsic values, that they are supposed to be about. In the West, as famously explained by Étienne Gilson: The resultant science of ontology eo nomine became easy prey to Kant’s critique of the powers of abstract a priori reason. That critique would also diminish confidence in the ontological aspects of earlier metaphysical systems which trace, ultimately, to Parmenides; as well as to any intellectual intuition of some separate or absolute rational fact and the associated infallible and incorrigible axioms upon which scientific demonstration depends. Closely related, confidence in the knowability of intrinsic value also diminished, in tandem with the rise of the value-free and purely quantificational conceptions of science that dominate the present age.

In the spirit of several famous post-Kantian and later Islamaic metaphysicians, in this chapter we cast back, beyond Parmenides, to Heraclitus as the starting point of the metaphysical enterprise as well as of the developmental paradigm of metaphysics. The first section builds upon Jorge F. E. Gracia’s conception of metaphysics in terms of categories per se and their interrelations. A development of Gracia’s conception incorporates insights from R. G. Collingwood’s scale of forms and G. R. G. Mure’s conception of development. In the resultant synthesis, the interrelation of categories is conceived in terms of a developing series of categories. The second section situates Heraclitus as the founder of Western metaphysics in general and of the developmental paradigm in particular. The next section discuses aspects of the tension between the developmental and ontological aspects of Aristotle’s metaphysics and associated theory of scientific demonstration; these contributed to the eventual collapse of Aristotelian science. Finally, some basic ideas of mathematician William Lawvere’s adaptation of Hegel’s objective logic are formulated using the language of contemporary mathematical category and topos theory, a framework that holds out the exciting promise of doing for developmental metaphysics what symbolic logic has done for ontology. The preliminary result is illustrated via a metaphysical theory of Benedetto Croce.
This is a preprint draft of paper published in 2020: Chapter 1: On the Logical Character and Coherence of Islamic Economics. Volume: Handbook of Analytical Studies in Islamic Finance and Economics Edited by: Zamir Iqbal, Tarik Akin,... more
This is a preprint draft of paper published in 2020:

Chapter 1: On the Logical Character and Coherence of Islamic Economics.
Volume: Handbook of Analytical Studies in Islamic Finance and Economics
Edited by: Zamir Iqbal, Tarik Akin, Nabil El Maghrebi and Abbas Mirakhor
De Gruyter Studies in Islamic Economics, Finance and Business
Edited by: Abbas Mirakhor and Idris Samawi Hamid

For scholarly/academic citation, kindly use the published version of the paper, available here:

https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/9783110587920/html

ABSTRACT
There has been an intensifying rise of consciousness regarding Islam’s vision of the economy and economics and, on the other hand, there is also the emergence of a wilderness of logical incoherence with a rapidly developing “echo-chamber” mentality that retards intellectual discourse and saps the energies needed for advancement of this nascent discipline. A necessary, if not sufficient condition, for defining the concept “Islamic Economics” involves a determination of the logical, philosophical, and/or scientific parameters that govern i) the movement of consciousness and action within the particular sphere associated with the extension of that concept, as well as ii) the interrelation of that sphere with other general, relevant domains of human experience (e.g., realms of economic consciousness and action). This necessary condition involves, in part, determining whether the concept “Islamic Economics” is even coherent. Does the range of applicability of “Islamic” intersect with that of “economics” (in the contemporary sense of ‘economics’)? If not, then the concept “Islamic Economics” has no material extension and remains in the realm of shadows. Determining some exact sense in which “Islamic Economics” is coherent depends, in large part, on fulfilling the necessary condition sketched above.

This paper is inspired in part by the work of ʿAllāmah Shahīd M. B. Ṣadr. Based on his work on logic, he understood that the axiomatic structure of the “science” of the contemporary, dominant paradigm of economics is in direct contradiction with the logic of an Islamic Economics based, first and foremost, on the Qurʾān. For example, the logic of the Qurʾān demands an overcoming of the Cartesian dualism that dominates much of current discourse around Islamic Economics, as well as the ensuing scientism and fideism that it entails. The part of the logic of Islamic Economics that overcomes this dualism may be articulated in terms of objective logic, in both an informal manner (scale of forms) or a formal manner (category theory).

This paper includes the following sections:
1 Background
2 Universes of Discourse and Categorical Coherence
3 Science, Intrinsic Value, and Self-Transcendence
4 Objective Logic and Phenomenology of Consciousness and Action
4.1 Objective Logic and Subjective Logic
4.2 Two Dialectical Lynchpins
5 Two approaches to Objective Logic: Informal and Formal
5.1 Informal Objective Logic: Scale of Forms
5.2 Formal Objective Logic: Functors and Natural Transformations
6 Transcending Cartesian Dualism: the Monism of the Qurʾān
7 Towards a Science of Iqtiṣād
This 2019 paper discusses the biography, main works, legacy, and selected arcs in the philosophy of Shaykh Aḥmad al-Aḥsāʾī: 1. Biography (life, character, and charisma) 2. Works (with emphasis on his *opera majora*) 3. Legacy (students,... more
This 2019 paper discusses the biography, main works, legacy, and selected arcs in the philosophy of Shaykh Aḥmad al-Aḥsāʾī:

1. Biography (life, character, and charisma)
2. Works (with emphasis on his *opera majora*)
3. Legacy (students, licensees, Shaykhism, and later trends)
4. Selected Arcs in the Philosophy of Shaykh Aḥmad (background, dialectics (with mention of Hegel), engagement with the followers of Mullā Ṣadrā, and the overall position of dialectical metaphysics within the project of Islamaic Illuminationism, with mention of Heraclitus).

This is the penultimate proof of Chapter Two, Shaykh Aḥmad al-Aḥsāʾī, in Philosophy in Qajar Iran, edited by Reza Pourjavady.

For accurate academic citation and quotation, kindly use the final, published version -- available from the author upon request.

Or you may order the published version here:

https://brill.com/view/book/edcoll/9789004387843/BP000010.xml
This paper was originally published in 2002, as a book chapter in The Passions of the Soul in the Metamorphosis of Becoming (Islamic Philosophy and Occidental Phenomenology in Dialogue), edited by Anna-Teresa Tymienicka. Kluwer... more
This paper was originally published in 2002, as a book chapter in

The Passions of the Soul in the Metamorphosis of Becoming (Islamic Philosophy and Occidental Phenomenology in Dialogue), edited by Anna-Teresa Tymienicka. Kluwer Academic Publishers; pp. 199-215.

There are many things the author would change if he were to rewrite this. For example, the meta-linguistic context of "process philosophy" would be changed to "dialectical philosophy". Even at the time of publication the author fully recognized that the framework of "dialectic" would be crucial to an accurate reflection of the philosophy of Shaykh Aḥmad in general and of the existence essence distinction in particular. Work on the dialectical framework had not progressed far enough to warrant bringing it up in print at that time.

Future works will, inshaaAllah, take the framework of dialectic as the foundation for the Shaykh's metaphysics of process. For now, we will simply say that the position of of the Shaykh is one of "dialectical hylomorphism".
Research Interests:
This work treats the correlative concepts knowledge and opinion, in various senses. In all senses of ‘knowledge’ and ‘opinion’, a belief known to be true is knowledge; a belief not known to be true is opinion. In this sense of ‘belief’, a... more
This work treats the correlative concepts knowledge and opinion, in various senses. In all senses of ‘knowledge’ and ‘opinion’, a belief known to be true is knowledge; a belief not known to be true is opinion. In this sense of ‘belief’, a belief is a proposition thought to be true—perhaps, but not necessarily, known to be true. All knowledge is truth. Some but not all opinion is truth. Every proposition known to be true is believed to be true. Some but not every proposition believed to be true is known to be true. Our focus is thus on propositional belief (“belief-that”): the combination of propositional knowledge (“knowledge-that”) and propositional opinion (“opinion-that”). Each of a person’s beliefs, whether knowledge or opinion, is the end result of a particular thought process that continued during a particular time interval and ended at a particular time with a conclusive act—a judgment that something is the case. This work is mainly about beliefs in substantive informative propositions—not empty tautologies.

We also treat objectual knowledge (knowledge of objects in the broadest sense, or “knowledge-of”), operational knowledge (abilities and skills, “knowledge-how-to”, or “know-how”), and expert knowledge (expertise). Most points made in this work have been made by previous writers, but to the best of our knowledge, they have never before been collected into a coherent work accessible to a wide audience.
Research Interests:
While the popular press, pundits and even academics, continue to say that Islam is anti-development, nothing could be further from the truth. The authors set the record straight in an admirable piece of true scholarship. Islam promotes... more
While the popular press, pundits and even academics, continue to say that Islam is anti-development, nothing could be further from the truth. The authors set the record straight in an admirable piece of true scholarship. Islam promotes development, not the development that economists talked about fifty years ago but what economists today espouse as sustainable and comprehensive development.

--
Hossein Askari
I, S  P is the second installment in the Islām-Dy- namic Project. In this exciting sequel to Islām, Sign and Creation, Idris Samawi Hamid constructs, for the first time ever in a Western language, a comprehensive and... more
I, S  P is the second installment in the Islām-Dy-
namic Project. In this exciting sequel to Islām, Sign and Creation, Idris
Samawi Hamid constructs, for the first time ever in a Western language,
a comprehensive and multi-dimensionaltopography of primordial Islāmic
spritual wayfaring. First, Hamid identifies the various stations of the journey.
Hethengivesanoverviewoftheprocessofmovingfromonelayertothenext,
ending finally with the full realization of the knowledge and love of God.
I, S  C is the first and foundational installment in the Islām-Dynamic Project. Here, Idris Samawi Hamid constructs a compre- hensive and general metaframework from which each genuinely Islāmic concept and process can... more
I, S  C is the first and foundational installment in the
Islām-Dynamic Project. Here, Idris Samawi Hamid constructs a compre-
hensive and general metaframework from which each genuinely Islāmic
concept and process can be defined and situated. The lynchpin of this
metaframework is the process of walāyah or dynamic loving. Within the
process of walāyah, Islām is seen to be, not a static dogma or absolutist
faith, but rather a path of seeking knowledge of the world, the self, and God.
This *draft* monograph consists of a translation, with notes and lexicon, of one of the most famous epitomes of Shīʿī theology: Al-Bāb ãl-Ḥādī ʿAshar (The Eleventh Chapter) by Jamāluddīn Ḥasan ibn Yūsuf al-Ḥillī (d. 726hl/1325ce), better... more
This *draft* monograph consists of a translation, with notes and lexicon, of one of the most famous epitomes of Shīʿī theology: Al-Bāb ãl-Ḥādī ʿAshar (The Eleventh Chapter) by Jamāluddīn Ḥasan ibn Yūsuf al-Ḥillī (d. 726hl/1325ce), better known as ʿAllāmah Ḥillī. A version of this is currently scheduled to be published as part of the book series

Collection of Al-Bāb al-Hādī ʿAshar: Commentaries and Translations, edited by Reza Yahyapour Farmad. Al-ʿAtabah al-Ḥusayniyyah, Karbala.
One of the objectives of the Oriental TeX project has always been to play with para- graph optimization. The original assumption was that we needed an advanced non- standard paragraph builder to Arabic done right but in the end we found... more
One of the objectives of the Oriental TeX project has always been to play with para- graph optimization. The original assumption was that we needed an advanced non- standard paragraph builder to Arabic done right but in the end we found out that a more straightforward approach is to use a sophisticated OpenType font in com- bination with a paragraph postprocessor that uses the advanced font capabilities. This solution is somewhat easier to realise than a complex paragraph builder but still involves quite some juggling. The lack of advanced fonts does not prevent us from showing what we’re dealing with. This is because the ConTeXt mechanisms are generic in the sense that they can also be used with regular Latin fonts, although it does not make that much sense. Anyhow, in the next section we wrap up the current state of typesetting Arabic in ConTeXt. We focus on the rendering, and leave general aspects of bidirectional typesetting and layouts for another time. This article is written by Idris Samawi Hamid and Hans Hagen and is typeset by ConTeXt MkIV which uses LuaTeX. Thisprogram is an extension of TeX that uses Lua to open up the core machinery. The LuaTeX core team consists of Taco Hoekwater, Hartmut Henkel and Hans Hagen. The launch of the LuaTeX project was sponsored in part by a grant from Colorado State University secured by Professor Idris Samawi Hamid.
ABSTRACT c.r. by Gilliot of: Osman Bakar, Foreword by Seyyed Hossein Nasr, Classification of knowledge in Islam, Cambridge, The Islamic Texts Society, 1998, XVII+312 p. ; Stud. Isl., 93 (2001), p. 152-3 (G. 5.2.239. )
1 The background of Oriental TEX Attempts to integrate scripts beyond the Latin into the TEX universe are nearly as old as TEX itself. In the case of Right-to-Left (RTL) scripts as Arabic script, the inadequacy of the original TEX to the... more
1 The background of Oriental TEX Attempts to integrate scripts beyond the Latin into the TEX universe are nearly as old as TEX itself. In the case of Right-to-Left (RTL) scripts as Arabic script, the inadequacy of the original TEX to the task was pointed out bluntly by Knuth himself back in 1987. Since then, the heroic efforts of the ArabTEX and Omega projects took large strides in the way of extending TEX to support Arabic-script typesetting. On the other hand, by the early 2000s the realization of a paradigm capable of capturing the fullness of the Arabic script and its sophistication still seemed a long ways away. Combined with other challenges, e.g., critical-edition typesetting, so much work remained to be done. In the winter of 2005–6, this author, along with Hans Hagen and Taco Hoekwater, initiated a very ambitious attempt to address the challenges of Arabicscript and critical-edition typesetting in the context of a radical overhaul and extension of TEX that would affect and ...
ABSTRACT FORTHCOMING BULLETIN OF SYMBOLIC LOGIC ►JOHN CORCORAN AND IDRIS SAMAWI HAMID, Two-method errors: having it both ways. Philosophy, University at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 14260-4150, USA E-mail: corcoran@buffalo.edu Philosophy,... more
ABSTRACT FORTHCOMING BULLETIN OF SYMBOLIC LOGIC ►JOHN CORCORAN AND IDRIS SAMAWI HAMID, Two-method errors: having it both ways. Philosophy, University at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 14260-4150, USA E-mail: corcoran@buffalo.edu Philosophy, Colorado State University, Fort Collins, CO 80523-1781 USA E-mail: ishamid@colostate.edu Where two methods produce similar results, mixing the two sometimes creates errors we call two-method errors, TMEs: in style, syntax, semantics, pragmatics, implicature, logic, or action. This lecture analyzes examples found in technical and in non-technical contexts. One can say “Abe knows whether Ben draws” in two other ways: ‘Abe knows whether or not Ben draws’ or ‘Abe knows whether Ben draws or not’. But a stylistic TME occurs in ‘Abe knows whether or not Ben draws or not’. One can say “Abe knows how Ben looks” using ‘Abe knows what Ben looks like’. But syntactical TMEs are in ‘Abe knows what Ben looks’ and in ‘Abe knows how Ben looks like’. One can deny that Abe knows Ben by prefixing ‘It isn’t that’ or by interpolating ‘doesn’t’. But a pragmatic TME occurs in trying to deny that Abe knows Ben by using ‘It isn’t that Abe doesn’t know Ben’. There are several standard ways of defining truth using sequences. Quine’s discussions in the 1970 first printing of Philosophy of logic [3] and in previous lectures were vitiated by mixing two [1, p. 98]. The logical TME in [3], which eluded Quine’s colleagues, was corrected in the 1978 sixth printing [2]. But Quine never explicitly acknowledged, described, or even mentioned the error. This lecture presents and analyses two-method errors in the logic literature. [1] JOHN CORCORAN, Review of Quine’s 1970 Philosophy of Logic. In Philosophy of Science, vol. 39 (1972), pp. 97–99. [2] JOHN CORCORAN, Review of sixth printing of Quine’s 1970 Philosophy of Logic. In Mathematical Reviews MR0469684 (1979): 57 #9465. [3] WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE, Philosophy of logic, Harvard, 1970/1986. END OF ABSTRACT THE PDF HAS OVER A DOZEN EXAMPLES. MAKE IT A BAKER'S DOZEN. PhD in Philosophy: State University of New York (SUNY) at University at Buffalo One possibility is PhD in Philosophy: State University of New York at Buffalo(SUNY). Another is PhD in Philosophy: University at Buffalo, State University of New York (SUNY)
The subject of this study is the process metaphysics and cosmology of Shaykh ’Ah.mad ibn Zayn al-Dīn al-’Ah. sā’̄i (d. 1826), especially as outlined in al-Fawā’id al-H. ikmiyyah (The Wisdom Observations), his philosophical epitome, which... more
The subject of this study is the process metaphysics and cosmology of Shaykh ’Ah.mad ibn Zayn al-Dīn al-’Ah. sā’̄i (d. 1826), especially as outlined in al-Fawā’id al-H. ikmiyyah (The Wisdom Observations), his philosophical epitome, which we have edited and translated. With Shaykh ’Ah.mad ended the cycle of the great and original philosophers of traditional Muslim civilization, a cycle that began with al-Kindi (d. 870). Shaykh ’Ah.mad belonged to the period of Muslim scholasticism that stemmed from the work of both the kalām theologian Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāz̄i (d. 1209) and the last great philosopher in the post-Hellenic tradition, Nas.̄ir al-Dīn al-T. ūs̄i (d. 1274). In particular, Shaykh ’Ah.mad worked two centuries after Mulla S.adra (d. 1640–41). The latter, through his theory of motion in the category of substance, marked the beginning of a turn towards process philosophy in Muslim scholasticism, a turn marked by a still strict adherence to Peripatetic method. My general contention...
This work treats the correlative concepts knowledge and opinion, in various senses. In all senses of ‘knowledge’ and ‘opinion’, a belief known to be true is knowledge; a belief not known to be true is opinion. In this sense of ‘belief’, a... more
This work treats the correlative concepts knowledge and opinion, in various senses. In all senses of ‘knowledge’ and ‘opinion’, a belief known to be true is knowledge; a belief not known to be true is opinion. In this sense of ‘belief’, a belief is a proposition thought to be true—perhaps, but not necessarily, known to be true. All knowledge is truth. Some but not all opinion is truth. Every proposition known to be true is believed to be true. Some but not every proposition believed to be true is known to be true. Our focus is thus on propositional belief (“belief-that”): the combination of propositional knowledge (“knowledge-that”) and propositional opinion (“opinion-that”). Each of a person’s beliefs, whether knowledge or opinion, is the end result of a particular thought process that continued during a particular time interval and ended at a particular time with a conclusive act—a judgment that something is the case. This work is mainly about beliefs in substantive informative propositions—not empty tautologies.
We also treat objectual knowledge (knowledge of objects in the broadest sense, or “knowledge-of”), operational knowledge (abilities and skills, “knowledge-how-to”, or “know-how”), and expert knowledge (expertise). Most points made in this work have been made by previous writers, but to the best of our knowledge, they have never before been collected into a coherent work accessible to a wide audience.

Key words:
belief, knowledge/opinion, propositional, operational, objectual, cognition, Gettier
Research Interests:
ABSTRACT FORTHCOMING BULLETIN OF SYMBOLIC LOGIC ►JOHN CORCORAN AND IDRIS SAMAWI HAMID, Two-method errors: having it both ways. Philosophy, University at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 14260-4150, USA E-mail: corcoran@buffalo.edu Philosophy,... more
ABSTRACT FORTHCOMING BULLETIN OF SYMBOLIC LOGIC

►JOHN CORCORAN AND IDRIS SAMAWI HAMID, Two-method errors: having it both ways.
Philosophy, University at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 14260-4150, USA
E-mail: corcoran@buffalo.edu
Philosophy, Colorado State University, Fort Collins, CO 80523-1781 USA
E-mail: ishamid@colostate.edu
  Where two methods produce similar results, mixing the two sometimes creates errors we call two-method errors, TMEs: in style, syntax, semantics, pragmatics, implicature, logic, or action. This lecture analyzes examples found in technical and in non-technical contexts.
  One can say “Abe knows whether Ben draws” in two other ways: ‘Abe knows whether or not Ben draws’ or ‘Abe knows whether Ben draws or not’. But a stylistic TME occurs in ‘Abe knows whether or not Ben draws or not’.
  One can say “Abe knows how Ben looks” using ‘Abe knows what Ben looks like’. But syntactical TMEs are in ‘Abe knows what Ben looks’ and in ‘Abe knows how Ben looks like’.
  One can deny that Abe knows Ben by prefixing ‘It isn’t that’ or by interpolating ‘doesn’t’. But a pragmatic TME occurs in trying to deny that Abe knows Ben by using ‘It isn’t that Abe doesn’t know Ben’.
  There are several standard ways of defining truth using sequences. Quine’s discussions in the 1970 first printing of Philosophy of logic [3] and in previous lectures were vitiated by mixing two [1, p. 98]. The logical TME in [3], which eluded Quine’s colleagues, was corrected in the 1978 sixth printing [2]. But Quine never explicitly acknowledged, described, or even mentioned the error.
  This lecture presents and analyses two-method errors in the logic literature.
  [1] JOHN CORCORAN, Review of Quine’s 1970 Philosophy of Logic. In Philosophy of Science, vol. 39 (1972), pp. 97–99.
  [2] JOHN CORCORAN, Review of sixth printing of Quine’s 1970 Philosophy of Logic. In Mathematical Reviews MR0469684 (1979): 57 #9465.
  [3] WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE, Philosophy of logic, Harvard, 1970/1986.
END OF ABSTRACT
THE PDF HAS OVER A DOZEN EXAMPLES. MAKE IT A BAKER'S DOZEN.
PhD in Philosophy: State University of New York (SUNY) at University at Buffalo
One possibility is PhD in Philosophy: State University of New York at Buffalo(SUNY).
Another is PhD in Philosophy: University at Buffalo, State University of New York (SUNY)
Research Interests:
This work treats the correlative concepts knowledge and opinion, in various senses. In all senses of ‘knowledge’ and ‘opinion’, a belief known to be true is knowledge; a belief not known to be true is opinion. In this sense of ‘belief’, a... more
This work treats the correlative concepts knowledge and opinion, in various senses. In all senses of ‘knowledge’ and ‘opinion’, a belief known to be true is knowledge; a belief not known to be true is opinion. In this sense of ‘belief’, a belief is a proposition thought to be true—perhaps, but not necessarily, known to be true. All knowledge is truth. Some but not all opinion is truth. Every proposition known to be true is believed to be true. Some but not every proposition believed to be true is known to be true. Our focus is thus on propositional belief (“belief-that”): the combination of propositional knowledge (“knowledge-that”) and propositional opinion (“opinion-that”). Each of a person’s beliefs, whether knowledge or opinion, is the end result of a particular thought process that continued during a particular time interval and ended at a particular time with a conclusive act—a judgment that something is the case. This work is mainly about beliefs in substantive informative pr...
A version of this paper was originally published in *International Journal of Decision Ethics*, Volume 1, Issue 2, pp. 125-149. Published in 2006, this paper is based on ideas developed several years earlier. It represents an early stab... more
A version of this paper was originally published in *International Journal of Decision Ethics*, Volume 1, Issue 2, pp. 125-149. Published in 2006, this paper is based on ideas developed several years earlier. It represents an early stab at developing the *philosophical* potential latent within the teaching of the Imams of the AhlulBayt (S) in the context of more contemporary philosophical concerns; in this case via a comparison and contrast with Kant's theory of the "good will". Among other things, this paper contains a rebuttal to C. D. Broad's claim that Kant's argument on the intrinsic goodness of the good will is fallacious.

There are some things the author would change in this paper if it were to be rewritten. For one, the ideas in this article were developed at a time when the perspective of its author (on, e.g. a framework of comparative philosophy, Shīʿī sources) was more under the influence of Henry Corbin. For example, the author's use of 'prophetic', as in 'prophetic sources', has its roots in Corbin. There are other obvious influences as well, each of which needs to be critically revisited and reevaluated.

Corbin was one of the only philosophers to attempt to tap the philosophical potential latent in the teachings of the Imams and to place them in a wider philosophical context. As seminal as his work was and remains, Corbin's framework (one of Meta-Gnosticism) is significantly flawed in certain respects for purposes of situating the thought of the Imams (S). This author is currently working on an alternative philosophical framework.

Much work remains to be done for the research presented in this paper to reach any authoritative conclusions. As the afore-mentioned framework for situating the philosophical intentions of the AhlulBayt (S) becomes more mature, the author may revisit this discussion and bring it up to date. *Inshā Allāh*.
Research Interests:
This paper was originally published in Journal for Chinese, Islamic, and Indian Cultural Relations, Volume 1, Issue 2, pp. 67-86. It is based on ideas about seven years earlier. This paper constitutes, as indicated by the title, some... more
This paper was originally published in Journal for Chinese, Islamic, and Indian Cultural Relations, Volume 1, Issue 2, pp. 67-86. It is based on ideas about seven years earlier.

This paper constitutes, as indicated by the title, some introductory ideas on a comparative philosophy project. An ambitious aim of this project is to build upon and eventually supercede Toshihiko Izutsu's brilliant work *Sufism and Taoism* as the standard work in this field. Izutsu used the cosmology of Ibn Arabi as the main basis for his meta-linguistic framework of comparison between Islamic and Taoist mysticism. One crucial point of comparison that is left out by that framework is *alchemy*. As a related point: It is a contention of this author that the philosophical cosmology of Shaykh Aḥmad al-Aḥsāʾī will provide a much more useful framework for comparison. Indeed, although this is not mentioned in the paper, it appears that the cosmology of Shaykh Aḥmad is so compatible with that of Taoism that the former can legitimately *clarify* a number of points in early Taoist literature. The reverse is also true: Taoist cosmology will clarify things in Islamic and especially Shīʿī thought that have been made obscure by the imposition of Aristotelian philosophy upon Islam's primordial cosmological framework.

There are many things that the author would change if this introduction were to be rewriten.. Among them is making explicit the role of the metaphysics of *objective logic* and *dialectic* in the meta-language of comparison. The one mention of "Hegelian dialectic" is an echo of Henry Corbin's rejection of Hegel's allegedly historicist dialectic. This has little bearing per se on the metaphysical dialectic common to both Taoism and to Shīʿī cosmology. Despite that this author would now rewrite that sentence. Corbin's anti-dialectical *meta-historical* approach as something entirely separate from historical circumstances is no longer entirely tenable. Indeed, the first few paragraphs of this article point in that direction. The translation of 'kalām' by 'dialectical theology' is unfortunate. It is a common translation in the literature and a very misleading one. The word 'dialectic' is already ambiguous enough in philosophical usage; its use to translate 'kalām' only compounds its vagueness. In future work we intend to use 'dialectic' in accordance with a small set of very precise but related senses.
Research Interests:
This article was published in 2004 in International Journal of Shīʿī Studies, Volume 2, Number 1; pp. 121-158 (the pdf wrongly states 2003). It presents an introduction to the philosopher-mystic Mīrzā Muḥammad ʿAlī Šāhʾābādī (d. 1944),... more
This article was published in 2004 in International Journal of Shīʿī Studies, Volume 2, Number 1; pp. 121-158 (the pdf wrongly states 2003). It presents an introduction to the philosopher-mystic Mīrzā Muḥammad ʿAlī Šāhʾābādī (d. 1944), the teacher of and perhaps the single most important influence upon Imam Ruhullah Khumayni (d. 1989). Touched upon are his connections to Ibn ʿArabi,  Mullā Sadrā Shīrāzī, as well as Shaykh Ahmad al-Ahsāʾī. The latter theme is in need of further development.

Following this introduction, we present a *draft* selection from our critical edition of one of the Mirza's treatises: Al-Qurʾān wa ãl-ʿItraḧ (The Qurʾān and the Progeny).

It is our intention to return to this theme, and to finally complete and publish our critical edition of the full Rašaḥātu ãl-Biḥār. InshaaAllah.
Research Interests:
This long article was published in 2003 in Volume 1, Issue 1, of International Journal of Shīʿī Studies. Its theme is the aim, object, methodology, and ultimately definition of 'metaphysics’ according to Shaykh Aḥmad al-Aḥsāʾī (d.... more
This long article was published in 2003 in Volume 1, Issue 1, of International Journal of Shīʿī Studies. Its theme is the aim, object, methodology, and ultimately definition of 'metaphysics’ according to Shaykh Aḥmad al-Aḥsāʾī (d. 1826).

As well as this original article perhaps accomplished that task, there are numerous things its author would change now. Some matters in the writing of the Shaykh which were not clear at the time are much clearer now. Further, the philosophical maturity of the author has made significant progress since this article was published.

One crucial issue in need of explicit exposition is the *dialectical* nature of the metaphysics of the Shaykh, in contrast to the *ontological* approach of the followers of Mulla Sadra in particular, and Classical Islamic Philosophy and Illuminationism in general.

Another matter in need of work is the *prehensology* of the Shaykh (مشعر ج. مشاعر); we may contrast prehensology with *psychology*. The foundations are in this article, but much has been discovered since its publication.

InshaaAllah we will say more about this in future works.
Research Interests:
http://www.ctan.org/pkg/almfixed Arabic Latin Modern Fixed Regular. This is a fixed-width font for the purpose of editing and entering Arabic-script text. Every Arabic-script glyph (for a total of 1845 characters) in each Unicode-code... more
http://www.ctan.org/pkg/almfixed

Arabic Latin Modern Fixed Regular. This is a fixed-width font for the purpose of editing and entering Arabic-script text. Every Arabic-script glyph (for a total of 1845 characters) in each Unicode-code block is supported (up to Unicode 7.0) There are two versions of the font: otf and ttf. The unique feature of Arabic-Latin Modern lies in its treatment ofvowels and diacritics. Each vowel and diacritic may now be edited horizontally within any text editor or processor. The author believes this is the very first opentype Arabic font ever to have this capability. Editing complex Arabic texts will now be much easier to input and to proofread.
Research Interests:
Keynote lecture delivered at the “Religious Faith and Social and Applied Sciences Conference”, October 11, 2013. Utah Valley University. One of the peculiar features of modern Western civilization is the conceptual divide between, on... more
Keynote lecture delivered at the “Religious Faith and Social and Applied Sciences Conference”, October 11, 2013. Utah Valley University.

One of the peculiar features of modern Western civilization is the conceptual divide between, on the one hand the category of religious faith, where knowledge is supposedly rare or impossible; and the category of scientific knowledge which, it is generally assumed, is the sole repository of true knowledge. This position is well-exemplified in theoretical physicist Freeman Dyson’s book chapter, “The Two Windows”, in the Templeton Foundations’s How Large Is God: The Voices of Scientists and Theologians. I argue that this conceptual bifurcation, which has its roots in Traditional Christianity, has subconsciously and subjectively within Western civilization been carried over into the very conception of science itself. At the same time, the broad category “religion”, inclusive of scientia (gnosis) has been reduced to that of “faith” (where knowledge/scientia is impossible). Hence the bifurcation leads to a polarization of civilization into two irreconcilable extremes: fideism and scientism, each following its own internal subjective logic. In such a civilizational situation, projects that seek to apply religious faith to the sciences, or to apply science to the religions, are engaged in a category mistake. One promising avenue to overcoming this divide lies in the burgeoning theory of objective logic. Objective logic involves the identification of objective maps and transformations between two apparently different categories or universes of discourse. This allows the precise derivation of new concepts, or a new framework for old concepts, where the resultant concepts will then transcend the categories of investigation and yet provide a dialectical bridge between them.
Research Interests:
One of the objectives of the Oriental TeX project has always been to play with para- graph optimization. The original assumption was that we needed an advanced non- standard paragraph builder to Arabic done right but in the end we found... more
One of the objectives of the Oriental TeX project has always been to play with para- graph optimization. The original assumption was that we needed an advanced non- standard paragraph builder to Arabic done right but in the end we found out that a more straightforward approach is to use a sophisticated OpenType font in com- bination with a paragraph postprocessor that uses the advanced font capabilities. This solution is somewhat easier to realise than a complex paragraph builder but still involves quite some juggling.

The lack of advanced fonts does not prevent us from showing what we’re dealing with. This is because the ConTeXt mechanisms are generic in the sense that they can also be used with regular Latin fonts, although it does not make that much sense. Anyhow, in the next section we wrap up the current state of typesetting Arabic in ConTeXt. We focus on the rendering, and leave general aspects of bidirectional typesetting and layouts for another time.

This article is written by Idris Samawi Hamid and Hans Hagen and is typeset by ConTeXt MkIV which uses LuaTeX. Thisprogram is an extension of TeX that uses Lua to open up the core machinery. The LuaTeX core team consists of Taco Hoekwater, Hartmut Henkel and Hans Hagen. The launch of the LuaTeX project was sponsored in part by a grant from Colorado State University secured by Professor Idris Samawi Hamid.
Research Interests:
Two pdf files: research article and presentation. The most relevant torture test of Arabic-script typesetting and typography involves capturing the nuances of the Arabic used in traditional Qurʾ¯anic script, a task that involves much... more
Two pdf files: research article and presentation.

The most relevant torture test of Arabic-script typesetting and typography involves capturing the nuances of the Arabic used in traditional Qurʾ¯anic script, a task that involves much by way of multiple layers of diacritics, paragraph optimizations using stretching and shape alternates, as well as multilayered coloring.

The Oriental TeX project is proud to announce that it has reached the milepost of being able to represent these aspects of Qurʾānic typography, marking a major outward milepost in the forward movement of Oriental TEX. There is still a ways to go, but in the current visual results we can confidently say that we are “over the hump” so to speak.
Research Interests:
The Oriental TeX project is an ambitious attempt to bring high quality Arabicscript typesetting to academics and, beyond, to the world at large. Recent decades have witnessed the degradation of typographical and typesetting quality of... more
The Oriental TeX project is an ambitious attempt to bring high quality Arabicscript typesetting to academics and, beyond, to the world at large. Recent decades have witnessed the degradation of typographical and typesetting quality of Arabic-script texts, in particular scholarly books. For example, complete sets of vowel markings and diacritics, crucial for understanding the meaning of a given text, are rarely available or readily accessible. This and other features so essential to a culturally authentic representation of Arabic script are woefully lacking in even the most expensive word processors and layout programs. Compared to the corresponding situation in Latin typography Arabic script resides in a veritable dark age. For the current round of funding through DANTE e.V., we are focusing on a problem that is by no means limited to the Arabic script. It turns out that a subset of the problems Arabic-script typography can be solved in a manner that will be of equal benefit to Latin-script typography or, indeed, any other script. This is the implementation of a flexible OpenType layout engine within TeX itself.
Research Interests:
"While the popular press, pundits and even academics, continue to say that Islam is anti-development, nothing could be further from the truth. The authors set the record straight in an admirable piece of true scholarship. Islam... more
"While the popular press, pundits and even academics, continue to say that Islam is anti-development, nothing could be further from the truth. The authors set the record straight in an admirable piece of true scholarship. Islam promotes development, not the development that economists talked about fifty years ago but what economists today espouse as sustainable and comprehensive development. -- Hossein Askari"
A version of this review was published in 2003 in *Bulletin of the Middle East Studies Association*: Volume 36, Issue 2, Winter; pp. 206-207. As mentioned at the outset of this review, the matter of the classification of knowledge in... more
A version of this review was published in 2003 in *Bulletin of the Middle East Studies Association*: Volume 36, Issue 2, Winter; pp. 206-207.

As mentioned at the outset of this review, the matter of the classification of knowledge in Islam builds upon Aristotle. The review mentions the crucial role played by the Aristotelian theory of *definition*. Not mentioned but related and equally important is the Aristotelian theory of *special science* as developed in his *Posterior Analytics*. Whereas Aristotle couched this in terms of *genus*, today we speak (more comprehensively) of *universe of discourse*. In Aristotle, genera (=universes of discourse) are mutually exclusive. Further, the set of first principles of a given science (with respect to a genus and developed via *subjective logic*) are discontinuous with those of every other. It has been emphasized by a number of modern metaphysicians (G. R. G. Mure, Stanley Rosen, etc.) that within the Aristotelian framework (and by extension the Muslim civilization that followed it) a genuine cross-disciplinary *science of science* or *wisdom* is impossible.

Thus, as mentioned in the review (paraphrasing Bakar): Both al-Farābī the philosopher and Ghazzālī the apologetic theologian "recognize a sharp difference between the purely intellectual sciences and those based on revelation."

Beyond this review: In an *objective logic* of universes of discourse we seek to overcome this discontinuity. The *objective mappings* of the content of the universe of discourse (or genus) of a given science to other universes (also called *functors*) is indispensable to both defining that science as well as to establishing a coherent *science of science* that is constituted by genuine *wisdom*. The current project of this author (Objective Logic) points in this direction.
BookReview
Research Interests:
Do sentences denote truth-values? Church [1], Tarski [2], and Corcoran [3] use the verb ‘denote’, or synonymously ‘name’, for a string-to-entity relation: the four-character string ‘zero’ denotes the number zero, i.e., ‘zero’ denotes... more
Do sentences denote truth-values?

  Church [1], Tarski [2], and Corcoran [3] use the verb ‘denote’, or synonymously ‘name’, for a string-to-entity relation: the four-character string ‘zero’ denotes the number zero, i.e., ‘zero’ denotes zero. Zero isn’t a string. But, the entity denoted can be a string: the six-character string ‘‘zero’’ denotes the four-character string ‘zero’.
  Given this usage certain rules apply. Using ‘is’ for identity, if ‘Abe’ and ‘Ben’ both denote: Abe is Ben iff ‘Abe’ denotes Ben, Abe is Ben iff ‘Ben’ denotes Abe, ‘Abe’ denotes Ben iff ‘Ben’ denotes Abe, ‘Abe’ denotes Abe, etc.
  Sentences such as ‘one precedes two’ and ‘two precedes one’ have truth-values: truth or falsity—the former truth and the latter falsity. Being true or false is related to having a truth-value: ‘Abe is Ben’ is true (false) iff ‘Abe is Ben’ has the truth-value truth (falsity).
  Being a truth-value isn’t having a truth-value. Truth is a truth-value but it doesn’t have a truth-value. ‘Abe is Ben’ has a truth-value but it isn’t a truth-value. Being a truth-value isn’t being true or false.
  Notice that ‘Abe is Ben’ is ‘Abe is Ben’ but ‘Abe is Ben’ isn’t ‘Ben is Abe’: one begins with ‘A’, the other with ‘B’.
  Sentences result from putting ‘is’ or ‘isn’t’ between two consecutive occurrences of denoting strings. Thus, if ‘one precedes two’ and ‘two precedes one’ denote, whether they denotes truth-values or not, the following oddities are sentences.

One precedes two is one precedes two.
One precedes two isn’t two precedes one.

  This essay surveys evidence, whether conclusive or suggestive, proposed as bearing on the hypothesis that sentences denote truth-values—accepted by Church, neither accepted nor rejected by Tarski, but rejected by Corcoran.
  [1] ALONZO CHURCH, Introduction to Mathematical Logic, Princeton, 1956.
  [2] ALFRED TARSKI, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, Hackett, 1983.
  [3] JOHN CORCORAN, Sentence, proposition, judgment, statement, and fact, Many Sides of Logic, College Publications, 2009.

https://www.academia.edu/8841128/Sentence_Proposition_Judgment_Statement_and_Fact_Speaking_about_the_Written_English_Used_in_Logic
RELATED LINKS
https://www.academia.edu/s/e74c5e179a/truth-value-making-relations?source=link
https://www.academia.edu/34276803/Truth-values
https://www.academia.edu/s/d3aac6a90a/truth-values?source=link
https://www.academia.edu/32508373/Valores_de_verdad
Research Interests:
Church [1], Tarski [2], and other mathematically-oriented logicians use the adjectives concrete and abstract as in traditional subject-object epistemology where concrete thinking subjects make abstract judgments about concrete objects. In... more
Church [1], Tarski [2], and other mathematically-oriented logicians use the adjectives concrete and abstract as in traditional subject-object epistemology where concrete thinking subjects make abstract judgments about concrete objects. In some correspondence theories of truth, abstract propositions are true or false in virtue of concrete facts [3]. Teaching geometry requires distinguishing between concrete triangles and their abstract shapes. Besides absolute, or attributive, uses of concrete and abstract, we also find relative uses. Every sentence of the form p V q is more concrete than its form. Conversely, the form p V q is more abstract than any sentence having it. We survey uses and conspicuous non-uses in logic of concrete and abstract including cognates: to abstract, abstraction, etc. We also consider distinctions often confused or identified with concrete-abstract distinctions, e.g., physical/non-physical and individual/universal. We identify many occurrences of concrete as fillers: rhetorical expletives, deleting them leaves the sentences's propositional meanings intact. In this use, every example is a concrete example and every concrete example is an example. Equally empty substitutes come readily to mind: particular, specific, individual, and so on. Remarkably, Church [1] uses abstract frequently while completely avoiding concrete. However, in Tarski [2] the exact opposite holds: there concrete occurs frequently while abstract is largely absent. In primary senses, concrete and abstract are correlative adjectives like old and young. It is difficult to determine what is being conveyed by calling something concrete or abstract unless writers give examples where they would apply one and not the other and they present some indication of their criteria for applying each word. [1] ALONZO CHURCH, Introduction to Mathematical Logic, Princeton UP, 1956.
Research Interests:
Church, Tarski, and other mathematically-oriented logicians use cognates of the words object and subject—such as objective, subjective, objectively, subjectively, objectivity, and subjectivity—in senses related to those in traditional... more
Church, Tarski, and other mathematically-oriented logicians use cognates of the words object and subject—such as objective, subjective, objectively, subjectively, objectivity, and subjectivity—in senses related to those in traditional subject-object epistemology where thinking subjects make judgments about factual objects. We survey use and conspicuous non-use of such words in logic
Research Interests:
We survey use, misuse, and conspicuous non-use of two words, ‘meta-language’ and ‘object-language’—and their cognates and synonyms.
Research Interests:
The question of the logical and philosophical coherence of the concept " Islamic Economics " and that of the extension of that concept as a scientific discipline involve a dilemma in urgent need of clarification and address[1]. Two points... more
The question of the logical and philosophical coherence of the concept " Islamic Economics " and that of the extension of that concept as a scientific discipline involve a dilemma in urgent need of clarification and address[1]. Two points of attack stand out. 1) In the context of the current zeitgeist which absolutizes a discontinuity between religion and science, it appears that each side belongs to a distinct universe of discourse[2], and that the range of application of the properties belonging to one does not include the objects belonging to the other. This appears to entail the theoretical incoherence of " Islamic Economics " from the outset. 2) The context of the primordial Islāmic uses of expressions such as 'iqtiṣād' (and its cognates), as well as related expressions in the Qurʾān and the Ḥadīth, entail a universe of discourse of spiritual value, viz., taqwā, that appears to be distinctly different from that of contemporary economics. Even if one were to articulate taqwā as a scientific discipline[3], this second point appears to entail the theoretical discontinuity of " Islamic Economics " – in the strict sense of 'Islāmic' – from contemporary economic science. A coherent conception of Islamic Economics hinges in part upon a critical examination of the civilizationally-conditioned categories " religion " and " science ". This paper will contend that Islām is not a mere religion in the narrow sense, but also advocates a framework of science in the broad sense. It is also our contention that this broad sense of 'knowledge' and 'science' is more concrete than that of the current paradigm of science in the narrow sense, although it absorbs the latter as a special case. A closely-related and theoretically prior challenge for grounding a coherent philosophy and scientific foundation of Islamic Economics lies in the alleged discontinuity between economics and value (in an axiological sense)[4]. Overcoming this discontinuity will involve explicit use of objective logic, a formal discipline developed within contemporary mathematical category theory to i) subserve scientific transformations between two or more universes of discourse (= categories, toposes), with a view to ii) progressively develop the conceptual content of those universes[5]. Within this framework the authors will establish 1) the logical coherence of Islamic Economics; and 2) the scientific absorption of the universe of discourse of contemporary economics within that of Islamic Economics to constitute an objective-logical scale of forms[6].
Research Interests:
International Journal of Shīʿī Studies was launched as a biannual serial in 2003 in collaboration with Professor Parviz Morewedge, Director of Global Scholarly Publications. This author was invited by GSP to serve as Editor-in-Chief as... more
International Journal of Shīʿī Studies was launched as a biannual serial in 2003 in collaboration with Professor Parviz Morewedge, Director of Global Scholarly Publications. This author was invited by GSP to serve as Editor-in-Chief as well as Technical Editor; the latter position included developing an automated-typesetting framework in TeX and ConTeXt for the journal. This author served as Editor-in-Chief for over seven years, during which time he oversaw the preparation and release of nine issues, the last being Volume 4, Number 1. After that issue the editorial reins were returned to GSP.

International Journal of Shīʿī Studies was the first attempt in a Western language to provide a serial devoted to scholarship related to Tashayyuʿ or Shīʿī Islam. Work on this journal provided the author with the opportunity to experiment with a paradigm of scholarship not beholden to the agendas of traditional orientalism. One of the persistent myths and prejudices of orientalist scholarship is that objectivity is incompatible with a personal commitment to Islam. On the contrary, it is the scientistic (not to be confused with scientific) pretensions of a considerable segment of the orientalist paradigm that is affected by an irreducible subjectivity. Perhaps this author will write more on this topic on another occasion. The aim of International Journal of Shīʿī Studies was to provide a platform for a different paradigm, where the rigors of genuine objectivity could be pursued without prejudice towards the cosmological commitments of the authors.

Innovations of International Journal of Shīʿī Studies included the development and deployment of a new paradigm for the transliteration of Arabic script. More radical, perhaps, was the insistence that inaccurate and anachronistic orientalist locutions such as ‘Shi'ite’ and ‘Shi'ism’ be abandoned in favor of expressions that derive from the bowels of the tradition itself, viz., ‘Shīʿī’ and ‘Tashayyuʿ’. Moojan Momen,***** in his otherwise fair and balanced critical review of the first issue, misses the objective spirit of this point by a wide margin. It is this author's intention to address Momen's criticism on a future occasion by way of an abstract or perhaps more.

***** Iranian Studies, Vol. 38, No. 2 (Jun., 2005), pp. 335-337
Research Interests:
A continuing desideratum for ConTeXt is a user-friendly writing and editing environment, where the range of application of the category “user-friendly” includes especially non-experts in programming or software development. The lack of... more
A continuing desideratum for ConTeXt is a user-friendly writing and editing environment, where the range of application of the category “user-friendly” includes especially non-experts in programming or software development. The lack of such an environment is one factor that inhibits the wider use of ConTeXt. Despite its immense power, precision, and flexibility: At present it is not generally feasible for instructors and researchers in, e.g., the humanities to assign the use of ConTeXt to students, or to use it to collaborate on projects.

In addition, the first author (Idris) especially required a ConTeXt editor with, among other features, bidirectional capabilities to serve both academic writing as well as the needs of the Oriental TeX project, including the Zahrāʾ typeface system under current development. In the course of an ongoing effort to address these lacunae, in 2017 a project to develop a set of utilities for the Windows text editor Notepad++ was launched. The first public version has been released:

Notepad++ for ConTeXt: Lexer and Macro Utilities for editing ConTeXt Documents
Version 0.98

This package includes

I. A plugin for Notepad++ that implements, for the ConTeXt document processing system,
i)  a language lexer for semantic highlighting of TeX, LuaTeX, and ConTeXt commands;
ii)  autocompletion of commands with full support for calltips (set in columns);
iii) tagging and insertion of markup and templates, with support for mnemonic keys.

II. A color scheme and two complementary Notepad++ themes:
Silver Twilight Hi and Silver Twilight Lo.

Notepad++ for ConTeXt is available here:

https://github.com/luigiScarso/context-npp
https://github.com/luigiScarso/context-npp/blob/master/install/Npp-for-ConTeXt.zip

as well as here:

http://wiki.contextgarden.net/File:Npp-for-ConTeXt.zip

For a future TeXLive DVD: The package will be available under

texmf-dist/context/data/npp/context

This paper constitutes the complete manual for Notepad++ ConTeXt. The TeX sources may be found in the following directory of the zip package:

/Npp-for-ConTeXt/doc/npp-context-manual.pdf

They are also available here:
https://github.com/luigiScarso/context-npp/tree/master/doc
Research Interests: